Female genital mutilation: multiple practices, multiple wrongs.

نویسنده

  • Michael Dunn
چکیده

Sitting down to write this editorial on 6 February, the Global ‘Day of Zero Tolerance’ for female genital mutilation (FGM), it feels somewhat disconcerting to be introducing a feature article arguing for a ‘compromise position’ towards a practice that is widely accepted as abhorrent. Indeed, I’m sure many of the journal’s readers will share my intuitive response that there is little scope for ethical disagreement on this issue, particularly in light of recent evidence that suggests that at least 200 million girls and women alive today have been subjected to this practice. Here, I introduce the collection of papers on FGM in this issue, expanding briefly upon the main arguments and counter-arguments put forward. The main argument is controversial, but its airing on the pages of the journal has a clear purpose: by subjecting FGM in its many forms to ethical analysis, we will be in a stronger position to develop and tailor interventions that function to prevent indefensible practices of this kind. Arora and Jacobs’s paper has a number of complementary aims. They begin by seeking to re-characterise FGM i practices by introducing a typology based on the functional impact of the procedure. They go on to argue against prohibiting procedures that have no lasting effect on morphology or function if performed correctly (which they refer to as ‘Category 1’, or the de minimis category, of FGM procedures), and that they believe would include such practices as making a small nick in the vulvar skin. Categorically, Arora and Jacobs are not arguing that all forms of FGM ought to be permitted; their claim is that prohibiting de minimis procedures will allow for cultural values in communities to be shown appropriate respect, whilst simultaneously enabling successful interventions to be taken to prohibit other FGM procedures that have long-term harmful consequences for the individual concerned. Whilst this proposal might look radical, it actually follows a well-trod pathway in public health policymaking whereby harm reduction strategies are adopted to address the harmful consequences associated with certain human behaviours. The three commentaries focus on both empirical and ethical concerns with this proposal. In empirical terms, questions are raised about whether, in practice, the aims of harm reduction would be met. Macklin points to evidence about cultural attitudes that suggests that those who endorse and practice FGM would not be motivated to shift their behaviour towards less harmful procedures. Shahvisi concurs, drawing on anthropological research to suggest that Arora and Jacobs’ strategy would face significant difficulties when applied in some cultural contexts. The ethical objections to Arora and Jacobs focus on the inadequacy of an argument that is focused on the degree of harm that FGM causes to the females involved. Objections of this kind are written into public policy statements, 3 which link the wrongfulness of FGM to a fundamental human rights violation that transcends any attempt to differentiate between types of FGM, and which seeks to design interventions that completely eradicate the practice. In her commentary, Macklin agrees with Arora and Jacobs that the de minimis category of FGM should not be considered as a human rights violation. The incongruity here need not trouble us so much; it is likely to be merely indicative of the fact that the assertion of human rights-based arguments can often function to muddy, rather than clarify, the terms of the ethical debate. Indeed, when we look in closer detail at the arguments developed by Macklin and relevant international agencies, we see the same central ethical concern being rehearsed: that FGM reflects and propagates problematic gender norms within some societies in ways that increase discrimination towards, and the exercise of control over, females. Whilst Arora and Jacobs dispute this constitutive relationship between FGM and gender oppression, the concern that adopting a compromise position would set back political attempts to address gender discrimination looks to be worthy of further attention. However, I take it there is a strong sense that we want to explain the wrongfulness of FGM in terms of what the practice involves for the specific girl or woman concerned, not merely because of what it symbolises or because of its wider relationship with gender justice in societies. Given Arora and Jacobs’ arguments, it is important to consider whether we can capture this individual-level wrongfulness in ways that apply to cases where the procedure causes no pain or distress, or has no long-term medical consequences. Earp looks to develop such an account when he argues that a person’s genitals might have a special psychosexual significance. However, for Earp this significance still boils down to (future) harm-related considerations: nonconsented procedures on genitalia are likely to be experienced as especially harmful by a person later in her life. Whilst Earp’s argument here picks up something significant about the diachronic nature of the subjective experience of harms, it does not quite capture other ways in which FGM wrongs (rather than harms) the individual on whom it is performed. Here, one might helpfully look for guidance towards those arguments that have sought to clarify the wrongs associated with rape. In an important contribution in this literature, the special interest that a person has in her ‘sexual integrity’ is outlined: a central component of a person’s interests that is worthy of respect because of its fundamental relationship to personhood, rather than because of the value the person places upon sex or sexual activity in her own life. On this account, rape is “very wrongful for violating what we are” (ibid, p.390). Whilst further work would be needed to clarify the conceptual connection between the ritualistic practices of FGM and female sexual identity, and between the notion of personhood and a conception of individuals’ ‘central’ interests, it is fruitful to think that this line of reasoning might be extended to provide an additional account of the wrongdoing involved in FGM procedures of all kinds.

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

The Nexus between Female Genital Mutilation and Child Marriage in Nigeria: A Cultural Inhibition to Achieving Sustainable Development Goals

The world leaders agreed to make the world a better place by year 2030 through the Sustainable Development Goals and targets. This however cannot be achieved in Nigeria except we are proactive about some cultural practices that negatively affect the girl child.  Child Marriage and Female Genital Mutilation/Cutting (FGM/C) are two deep-rooted Harmful Traditional Practices (HTPs) that have prevai...

متن کامل

P-178: Female Genital Mutilation: The Jewish, Christian and Islamic Views

Background: Female genital mutilation (FGM) is a practice involving the removal of all or parts of the female external genitalia.It has been documented in 28 African countries and in some countries in Asia and the Middle East,but due to increasing immigration from these countries to the western world,FGM has become a worldwide human rights and health issue. Materials and Methods: This paper is ...

متن کامل

A case report of genital self-mutilation in a patient with psychosis

Background: Self-mutilation is one of the most extreme types of self-harm, which is done deliberately to hurt the body, regardless of suicidal intent. In self-mutilation, the most important targets are the eyes, genital tract, and hands. So far, genital self-mutilation (GSM) has been less frequently reported around the world. According to our study, this is the first case of GSM reported in Ira...

متن کامل

Female Genital Mutilation in Sudan

BACKGROUND Female genital mutilation or female circumcision (FGM) is a serious health problem in Sudan. This procedure is harmful to women and causes many complications during pregnancy and childbirth. OBJECTIVE This study aims to determine the female genital mutilation (FGM) and its associated factors in Sudan. SUBJECTS AND METHODS Data from Sudan Multiple Indicator Cluster Survey (MICS - ...

متن کامل

Female genital mutilation/cutting in Africa

Female genital mutilation/cutting (FGM/C) is a traditional practice in which the external female genitalia is partially or totally incised or excised for a non-therapeutic reason, usually without the consent of the individual. FGM/C is common in Africa with varying prevalence in different countries, though the incidence is reducing because it is considered a human rights issue with tremendous a...

متن کامل

O-17: Female Genital Mutilation: A Curse or Blessing among Women of Reproductive Age in Nigeria

Background: Female genital mutilation (FGM) practice is mostly carried out by traditional circumcisers, who often play other central roles in communities, such as attending childbirths. Increasingly, FGM is also performed by health care providers. However, FGM is recognized internationally as a violation of the human rights of girls and women. The study investigates a broad cross-cultural study...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:
  • Journal of medical ethics

دوره 42 3  شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2016